翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ "O" Is for Outlaw
・ "O"-Jung.Ban.Hap.
・ "Ode-to-Napoleon" hexachord
・ "Oh Yeah!" Live
・ "Our Contemporary" regional art exhibition (Leningrad, 1975)
・ "P" Is for Peril
・ "Pimpernel" Smith
・ "Polish death camp" controversy
・ "Pro knigi" ("About books")
・ "Prosopa" Greek Television Awards
・ "Pussy Cats" Starring the Walkmen
・ "Q" Is for Quarry
・ "R" Is for Ricochet
・ "R" The King (2016 film)
・ "Rags" Ragland
・ ! (album)
・ ! (disambiguation)
・ !!
・ !!!
・ !!! (album)
・ !!Destroy-Oh-Boy!!
・ !Action Pact!
・ !Arriba! La Pachanga
・ !Hero
・ !Hero (album)
・ !Kung language
・ !Oka Tokat
・ !PAUS3
・ !T.O.O.H.!
・ !Women Art Revolution


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

Mu calculus : ウィキペディア英語版
Modal μ-calculus
In theoretical computer science, the modal μ-calculus (Lμ, Lμ, sometimes just μ-calculus, although this can have a more general meaning) is an extension of propositional modal logic (with many modalities) by adding a least fixpoint operator μ and a greatest fixpoint operator \nu, thus a fixed-point logic.
The (propositional, modal) μ-calculus originates with Dana Scott and Jaco de Bakker,〔Kozen p. 333.〕 and was further developed by Dexter Kozen into the version most used nowadays. It is used to describe properties of labelled transition systems and for verifying these properties. Many temporal logics can be encoded in the μ-calculus, including CTL
*
and its widely used fragments—linear temporal logic and computational tree logic.〔Clarke p.108, Theorem 6; Emerson p. 196〕
An algebraic view is to see it as an algebra of monotonic functions over a complete lattice, with operators consisting of functional composition plus the least and greatest fixed point operators; from this viewpoint, the modal μ-calculus is over the lattice of a power set algebra.〔Arnold and Niwiński, pp. viii-x and chapter 6〕 The game semantics of μ-calculus is related to two-player games with perfect information, particularly infinite parity games.〔Arnold and Niwiński, pp. viii-x and chapter 4〕
== Syntax ==
Let ''P'' (propositions) and ''A'' (actions) be two finite sets of symbols, and let ''V'' be a countably infinite set of variables. The set of formulas of (propositional, modal) μ-calculus is defined as follows:
* each proposition and each variable is a formula;
* if \phi and \psi are formulas, then \phi \wedge \psi is a formula.
* if \phi is a formula, then \neg \phi is a formula;
* if \phi is a formula and a is an action, then () \phi is a formula;(pronounced either: a box \phi or after a necessarily \phi)
* if \phi is a formula and Z a variable, then \nu Z. \phi is a formula, provided that every free occurrence of Z in \phi occurs positively, i.e. within the scope of an even number of negations.
(The notions of free and bound variables are as usual, where \nu is the only binding operator.)
Given the above definitions, we can enrich the syntax with:
* \phi \lor \psi meaning \neg (\neg \phi \land \neg \psi)
* \langle a \rangle \phi (pronounced either: a diamond \phi or after a possibly \phi) meaning \neg () \neg \phi
* \mu Z. \phi means \neg \nu Z. \neg \phi (Z ), where \phi (Z ) means substituting \neg Z for ''Z'' in all free occurrences of ''Z'' in \phi .
The first two formulas are the familiar ones from the classical propositional calculus and respectively the minimal multimodal logic K.
The notation \mu Z. \phi (and its dual) are inspired from the lambda calculus; the intent is to denote the least (and respectively greatest) fixed point of the expression \phi where the "minimization" (and respectively "maximization") are in the variable ''Z'', much like in lambda calculus \lambda Z. \phi is a function with formula \phi in bound variable ''Z'';〔Arnold and Niwiński, p. 14〕 see the denotational semantics below for details.

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「Modal μ-calculus」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.